Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
the organized body of knowledge, or science, that evaluates arguments. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
a group of statements, the purport of which is that some of them (the premises) should support, imply, provide evidence for, or make reasonable to believe another particular one of them (the conclusion). |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
set forth the reasons for the conclusions; the conclusion is meant to follow from these reasons. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
those in which the premises really do support, imply, provide evidence for, or make reasonable to believe the conclusion |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
those in which the premises do not in fact support, etc. the conclusion, even though the argument purports that they do so |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
thus
therefore consequently hence so it follows that proves that indicates that *accordingly implies that *for this reason as a result we can infer this means entails that implies that
|
|
|
Term
|
Definition
for since as because for the reason follows from after all in light of the fact *for the reason assuming that the reason is inasmuch as given that in view of granting that seeing that |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
the meaning-contents of statements. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
When the arguer claims that it is impossible for the conclusion to be false given that the premises are true, An argument is deductive if its purport is that it is impossible that its premises be true and its conclusion false. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
When the arguer merely claims that it is improbable that the conclusion be false given that the premises are true. An argument is inductive if its purport is merely that it is improbable that its premises be true and its conclusion false. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
if the argument employs such words as “necessarily,” “certainly,” or “absolutely,” it is usually best regarded as deductive. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
If expressions such as “probably,” “likely,” or “plausibly” are employed, the argument is usually best regarded as inductive. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
A deductive argument is valid if it is impossible for the conclusion to be false given that the premises are true. |
|
|
Term
Invalid Deductive Argument |
|
Definition
If there is any possibility that the premises could all be true and yet the conclusion false, then the argument is invalid. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
A sound argument is a deductive argument that is valid and has all true premises. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
A cogent argument is an inductive argument that is strong and has all true premises. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
A categorical proposition is a proposition that relates two classes, or categories, denoted respectively by the subject term and the predicate term. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
The words “all,” “no,” and “some” are called logical quantifiers. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
The words “are” and “are not” are called copulas. |
|
|
Term
Quality of a Categorical Proposition |
|
Definition
The quality of a categorical proposition is defined as affirmative if it affirms class membership (as do “All S are P” and “Some S are P”). The quality is negative if it does not affirm a class membership ( 'No S are P.' and 'Some S are not P.') |
|
|
Term
Quantity of a Categorical Proposition |
|
Definition
The quantity of a categorical proposition is defined as universal if it makes a claim about every member of the S class (as do “All S are P” and “No S are P”) and particular if it makes a claim about just some (at least one) member of the S class (as do “Some S are P” and “Some S are not P”). |
|
|
Term
Tradition or Aristotelian Sense |
|
Definition
If the propositions are taken to imply the existence of at least one member of the class denoted by their subject term “S,” and of at least one member of the class denoted by their predicate term “P,” then the proposition are being understood in the tradition or Aristotelian sense. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
If the propositions are not taken to imply the existence of at least one member of the class denoted by their subject term “S,” and of at least one member of the class denoted by their predicate term “P,” then the propositions are being understood in the modern or Boolean sense. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
Conversion consists of simply switching the subject term with the predicate term while leaving the quality and quantity of the proposition unaltered.
Example: “All dogs are mammals”
--> Converse -->
“All mammals are dogs.” |
|
|
Term
Logically equivalent claims for Converse |
|
Definition
|
|
Term
|
Definition
Obversion consists of both
(1) changing the quality of the proposition (leaving the quantity the same),
and
(2) complementing the predicate term. |
|
|
Term
Logically equivalent claims for Obversion |
|
Definition
The obverse of any categorical proposition, A, E, I or O, is logically equivalent to it. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
Contraposition consist of both
(1) switching the subject with the predicate term (while leaving the quality and quantity of the proposition unaltered),
and
(2) complementing both terms. |
|
|
Term
Logically equivalent claims for Contraposition |
|
Definition
A and O Propositions are logically equivalent. |
|
|
Term
|
Definition
To complement the predicate term, one typically attaches the prefix “non-“ to it. |
|
|